Skip to main content

Depression and decision-making capacity for treatment or research: a systematic review

Abstract

Background

Psychiatric disorders can pose problems in the assessment of decision-making capacity (DMC). This is so particularly where psychopathology is seen as the extreme end of a dimension that includes normality. Depression is an example of such a psychiatric disorder. Four abilities (understanding, appreciating, reasoning and ability to express a choice) are commonly assessed when determining DMC in psychiatry and uncertainty exists about the extent to which depression impacts capacity to make treatment or research participation decisions.

Methods

A systematic review of the medical ethical and empirical literature concerning depression and DMC was conducted. Medline, EMBASE and PsycInfo databases were searched for studies of depression and consent and DMC. Empirical studies and papers containing ethical analysis were extracted and analysed.

Results

17 publications were identified. The clinical ethics studies highlighted appreciation of information as the ability that can be impaired in depression, indicating that emotional factors can impact on DMC. The empirical studies reporting decision-making ability scores also highlighted impairment of appreciation but without evidence of strong impact. Measurement problems, however, looked likely. The frequency of clinical judgements of lack of DMC in people with depression varied greatly according to acuity of illness and whether judgements are structured or unstructured.

Conclusions

Depression can impair DMC especially if severe. Most evidence indicates appreciation as the ability primarily impaired by depressive illness. Understanding and measuring the appreciation ability in depression remains a problem in need of further research.

Peer Review reports

Background

Although jurisdictions vary in the wording of the abilities adult decision-makers are deemed to need in order to decide for themselves about treatment, an influential model has been outlined by Grisso & Appelbaum [1]. The model consists of four abilities.

  1. 1.

    The ability to express a choice

  2. 2.

    The ability to understand information relevant to treatment decision making

  3. 3.

    The ability to appreciate the significance of that information for one’s own situation, especially concerning one’s illness and the probable consequences of one’s treatment options; and

  4. 4.

    The ability to reason with the relevant information so as to engage in a logical process of weighing treatment options

The four abilities model can be used as a guide in both clinical and legal capacity judgments. Without the sufficient possession of any one of these four abilities, a patient may be considered unable to exercise their autonomy in relation to treatment decisions.a Suitably modified, this applies to other decisions such as research participation. There is a distinction between impairment of these decision-making abilities, which lie on continua and the judgment of DMC, which is binary. The DMC decision is ultimately normative and justifies allowing other stakeholders to make decisions on behalf of the patient.

Psychiatric disorders are risk factors for loss of DMC [2] but there is some debate about whether current models of decision-making capacity are able to accommodate the changes of emotion and value that can be seen in psychiatric disorders where understanding ability is often not impaired [36]. There is also the question of how much ability a patient requires to yield a categorical judgment of DMC [7] and the reliability of physician judgments [8]. Depression is significant in relation to these debates because of its high prevalence in health settings; its emotional nature; its dimensionality; and the often “understandable” quality of patient decision-making, which is perhaps best characterized by Appelbaum & Roth [9]:

“Of all the psychopathological processes associated with refusal [of treatment], depression is the most difficult to recognize, because it masquerades as, ‘Just the way I would think if it happened to me’ … The depressed patient is frequently able to offer ‘rational’ explanations for the choices that are made.”

If depression can impair DMC, then depressed individuals may be at risk of making treatment decisions without the abilities needed whilst being considered autonomous. The consequences of this are potentially disastrous; consider the case of John Smith, a man with progressive but nonetheless treatable respiratory failure and recognized severe depression. He refused medical treatment, dying without any attempt to cure his depression, despite the fact this known mental illness may well have altered his judgment and consequent DMC [10]. In such cases, ethical concerns arise about the protection of patient welfare.

We aimed to conduct a systematic review of medical and medical ethical research on depression and DMC. Our primary aims were (1) to review clinical ethical accounts of how DMC may be affected by depression and (2) to review the empirical literature and their measures of the impact of depression on DMC.

Methods

A search was carried out attempting to locate all the literature relevant to the aims of the review. Inclusion criteria required that selected papers were (1) in the English language; (2) included significant clinical ethical analysis or contained relevant observational data using DMC assessment tools in depressed individuals. Papers were excluded if they: (1) were in a foreign language; (2) did not contain empirical data relating to the legal/ethical standards of DMC; or (3) lacked substantial ethical analysis.

Relevant articles were selected by TH and GO through a systematic search of electronic databases. These comprised MEDLINE (1946 to February 2012), PsycINFO (1946 to February 2012) and EMBASE (1974 to February 2012).

Search terms included: 1) Depression, Depressive disorder, Depressed and 2) Decision-making, Informed consent, Competence, Mental competency, Mental capacity.

These search terms were combined (1. Ω 2.) in keyword searches of all three databases. Titles and abstracts were screened for eligibility and where relevant, studies were read in through to determine eligibility. Citations of eligible articles were also screened.

All studies with empirical data were included that used measures of DMC related to legal/ethical standards and involved treatment or research decisions.

Making a distinction within the non-empirical literature between studies with and without “substantive” ethical analysis may seem subjective, but was readily achievable in practice. Non-data papers were only included if they addressed the relation between depression and DMC using ethical constructs and reasoning. Many utilised case studies in illustrating this. Papers that were not included typically involved rehearsals of extant law or pragmatic considerations in specific clinical scenarios such as constraints of time or risk assessment. Papers excluded by TH were reviewed by GO and no disagreements were found.

Results

The search produced a total of 1585 papers (PsycINFO = 121, MEDLINE = 1299, EMBASE = 165). The titles of all articles generated were read and examined on the above inclusion and exclusion criteria, with abstracts of possible importance considered for inclusion. After removal of duplicates and further analysis of abstracts, an initial total of 30 articles were selected and read in full. Application of inclusion/exclusion criteria narrowed this to 13 in the final review. The search was augmented through examination of cited material within the selected papers for further relevant material suitable for inclusion. The citation search produced a further 2 articles suitable for inclusion, bringing the final total of articles to 15. Additionally, contact with fellow researchers in the field highlighted 2 further papers by Bean et al. which were also included (Figure 1).

Figure 1
figure 1

Summary of review methods.

The heterogeneous methods used within the 17 included papers made systematic quality assessment of the papers unsuitable for the review, but all studies were found to relate to legal standards pertinent to the review. Two studies were finally excluded because they only related to supported decision making rather than to DMC (See Tables 1 and 2).

Table 1 Results from clinical ethical analyses
Table 2 Results from Empirical Studies

Analysis of the material revealed a number of themes, which are presented in a narrative manner below.

We found 7 papers using ethical analysis of clinical case histories &/or acquired clinical experience.

Depressed patients lack appreciation

Several of the articles highlighted appreciation as the component of capacity lacking in depressed individuals. Grisso and Appelbaum in their four ability model give the following characterisation of appreciation; ‘[We] use the term in reference to people who, because of cognitive deficits or emotional states, fail to accept the relevance of their disorders or potential treatment consequences for their own circumstances.’[1]. In simple terms, the transition from simply understanding the medical facts, to actual application of those facts by an individual to their own situation, can be impaired in the depressed individual.

Leeman (1999) used two case studies involving end of life decisions in highlighting where lack of appreciation rendered an individual incompetent. He used two examples (including that of John Smith cited above) in demonstrating the importance of distinguishing understanding and appreciation. He argued for a distinction between factually restating the consequences of a treatment decision and consideration of the situation-dependent, personal implications of that decision. John Smith, he contended, required an assessment of these latter abilities.

Young et al. (1993) also explored mental capacity in depressed patients via means of case studies in which a request to die is made. These cases again illustrate scenarios when depression was seen to impair a patient’s ‘ability to comprehend the consequences of a choice’ , again indicating that appreciative ability is at stake in depressive illness.

Meynen (2011) approached the topic from a phenomenological perspective to highlight the insufficiencies depressed patients have in their appreciative abilities. According to Meynen, mentally competent individuals possess an online perception of the world as a network of possibilities, from which further possibilities extend exponentially. The perception of these possibilities is intimately related to emotion and mood, and affective disorders may give rise to distortions. In other words, judgments concerning treatment benefits and risks, and their personal consequences, may, in depression, become founded on a skewed and altered perception of future possibility and compromise appreciative ability.

Halpern (2012), like Leeman and Young et al., utilized a case study in illustrating the deficits in appreciative capacity some depressed individuals have. Through the case of Ms. G, she introduced the concept of ‘concretized emotion-belief complexes’ , whereby a person is so certain that their future contains a certain set of events (as a result of an emotional extreme) that they cannot truly appreciate the benefits or risks involved in their treatment decision. Under her model, emotions and cognitive factors are implicitly linked and so are able to interfere with each other. She goes on to explain that although a person in this state can engage in apparent deliberation, these thought processes are overwhelmingly characterized by the rigid conviction of their current belief as perceived from their fixed emotional view. True deliberation and appreciation requires that an individual ‘think[s] through alternatives, and this thinking through alternatives needs to be responsive to evidence’ . (Authors’ italics).

Accountability

Elliot (1997) addressed the capacity of depressed individuals from a different perspective, drawing moral responsibility into the picture. He set the threshold of capacity at the point where a patient can be considered accountable for their choice. Whilst accepting DMC could be influenced by both cognitive and emotional factors, he pinpointed two criteria required for accountability that are potentially compromised in depressed patients; namely, decisional authenticity and a minimal level of concern regarding one’s own welfare. Lack of ‘decisional authenticity’ refers to the fact that depressed individuals may not make decisions that reflect their ‘true’ autonomous self. Equally, they may not possess a minimal level of concern for their own welfare, without which any claim of DMC is jeopardized. Even when understanding and appreciative ability remain intact, Elliot argued, depressive illness may leave an individual with so little self concern regarding the potential negative outcomes of a research decision, that they cannot be considered accountable for their decision to participate. This, Elliot said, amounts to not caring about risks rather than not appreciating risks. Without decisional authenticity or minimal self-concern, patients cannot be considered accountable for their actions, as they are a manifestation of the affective disorder rather than the truly autonomous individual that exists behind the façade of illness.

Emotion, cognition and capacity

All the clinical ethical literature recognizes interplay between cognition, emotion and DMC. The widespread view is that capacity assessment must take into account both cognitive and emotional factors. An extract from Sullivan & Youngner’s (1994) review demonstrates how the (emotional) symptoms of depression (in bold) might correlate with deficits in the cognitive (understanding, appreciation and reasoning) components of mental capacity:

‘Depressive helplessness produces an underestimation of one’s possible effectiveness in the face of serious illness. Guilt and worthlessness may make one believe that suffering and death are deserved… Anhedonia may make it impossible to imagine that life will offer any pleasures for which it is worth enduring … illness. Depressive hopelessness can make it impossible to imagine that life will ever offer a better balance of pleasure and pain that it does at present.’

Rudnick (2002), however, argued that a degree of separation between emotion and cognition exists; suggesting that coherence of personal preference may be disrupted even when the four abilities that make up standard assessment of DMC remain unscathed by depression. He, like others, proposed a strategy by which depressed patients can be protected against their own treatment decision. By asking previously depressed individuals their preferences regarding treatment of any future episodes of depression, and matching these to treatment preferences expressed during the depressive period, DMC may be better assessed and autonomy better respected. However, he did concede that in the initial episode, depressed individuals should be treated in their ‘best interests’ until restored to health. This matter is discussed later.

MacCAT and other measures of DMC

Does depression impair performance on tests of decision-making capacity?

One of the earliest studies (Grisso & Appelbaum 1995) investigated hospitalised patients with major depression. A semi-structured interview was used to measure three of the four components of capacity to decide treatment (This was a precursor to the MacArthur Competence Assessment Tool – Treatment “MacCAT-T”), namely understanding, appreciation and reasoning ability. Of the ninety-two depressed participants, 23.9% (22/92) displayed an impairment in one or more of the assessed components, with half of these displaying an impairment in appreciation.

All but one of the included empirical data studies conducted after this date used the MacCAT and the four-ability model in measuring mental capacity. (Table 3).

Table 3 The MacArthur competency assessment tool[1]

Three studies included MacCAT data. In their 1999 study, Appelbaum et al. (1999) measured the MacCAT abilities of moderately depressed inpatients to consent to clinical research, modifying the MacCAT for this purpose (MacCAT-CR). Capacity measurements were made within one week of admission with a second assessment made 8–10 weeks later. Almost all subjects performed well on initial capacity measures, maintaining this over the course of their admission. Similar findings are reported by Cohen et al. (2004).

In Lapid et al. (2003) forty severely depressed patients (DSM-IV criteria) were measured on MacCAT-T abilities to consent to electro-convulsive therapy (ECT). Judgements of DMC were not made. Overall, participants displayed good baseline scores on the MacCAT abilities at initial measurement including appreciation. 11 patients (27.5%) had active psychotic symptoms at the time of interview. This group had lower scores on the appreciation subscale compared with the non-psychotic population but no statistically significant differences in understanding, reasoning, and choice. As part of the study, Lapid et al. trialed a standard and an experimental educational intervention, finding that both improved MacCAT ability scores, though ceiling effects made interpretation difficult.

Vollmann et al. (2003) looked at MacCAT-T scores in depressed inpatients and the separate judgment of a physician, who was instructed to judge capacity ‘freely on the basis of his or her own clinical experience.’ Using various combinations of cut offs scores for understanding, appreciation and reasoning to define “impairment”, a range of impairment from 2.9% to 20% was found. Within the same sample, the attending physician judged only one patient as lacking in DMC.

Owen et al. (2008) conducted a study involving 350 consecutive admissions to a psychiatric hospital 67 of which made up a depressive subset. The study aimed to assess the prevalence of impaired DMC using the MacCAT-T to structure a clinical judgment. The prevalence of incapacity was estimated to be 31% in the depressed subset. Severity of depressed mood associated with lack of DMC.

Bean et al. (1994/6) developed a 15-item semi-structured Competency Interview Schedule (CIS) to measure DMC. It is discussed in two papers where the DMC of 96 inpatients to consent to ECT was assessed. The majority of patients had major depressive illness. All participating subjects had their decisional capacity judged by their attending physician before undertaking the CIS and 21.9% were judged lacking capacity to decide whether to opt for/against ECT. The closest correlation between item scores and physician judgment of DMC was that requiring the patient to specify the potential benefits of the treatment.

Insight and DMC

Owen et al. (2009) further analysed the sample described in Owen et al. (2008). Two hundred participants in the study were subject to several assessments before judging DMC, including the MacCAT-T, the Expanded Schedule for the Assessment of Insight (SAI-E) and the Brief Psychiatric Rating Scale (BPRS). The relationship between insight (awareness of illness) and DMC was evaluated and found to be dependent on the disorder encountered. Whilst insight mapped to DMC well in illnesses like schizophrenia and mania, it mapped poorly in depressive illness (poor sensitivity) suggesting insight is not a good clinical indicator of DMC in depression. Severity of depressed mood associated strongly with DMC.

Regaining DMC

Owen et al. (2011) using the above cohort also looked at which broad diagnostic groups associate with regaining DMC. One month following admission, patients with depression were found to be more likely than patients with schizophrenia and related disorders to regain DMC indicating that change, or fluctuation, of DMC is more a feature of depression.

Discussion

This systematic review of the literature suggests that depression can impair DMC by impacting on appreciation and to a lesser degree, understanding and reasoning ability. Much depends upon illness severity and population studied. The literature is small and heterogeneous and so conclusions can only be tentative.

Clinical ethical analysis stresses appreciative ability as site of impairment. Different formulations of this inability exist in the literature and each is relatively unspecified. Two concepts seem to offer useful leads: Meynen (2010), Halpern (2010), and Sullivan & Youngner (1994) highlight an inability to appreciate future possibilities and Elliott (1997) highlights an inability to maintain a minimal concern for self. Both are viewed as normative inabilities that may threaten DMC. The affective symptoms of depression can theoretically distort [15] or blind [12] an individuals’ perception of the future, but as Meynen remarks, the ability to appreciate future possibilities needs, further specification and empirical testing [13]. Elliot presents the minimal concern for self concept as distinct from appreciation but this distinction depends upon the boundaries one places around the appreciation ability which seems sufficiently broadly defined to encompass minimal concern for self. It is also unclear how minimal concern for self differs from the trait of low self-esteem, which is common and is not diagnostic [26], and does not automatically confer lack of DMC.

The emphasis being put on appreciation in the clinical ethical studies is partly reflected in the empirical studies involving the MacCAT but it is weaker than the clinical ethical analysis would lead one to expect. Part of this may be explained by selection of cases with the clinical ethical analysis focusing on exceptional cases whilst the empirical studies take mixed populations of patients with varying levels of depression and different decisions (research and treatment). However, in the Lapid et al. (2003) study of severely depressed patients undergoing ECT, appreciation scores were high overall with only partial reduction seen in a subgroup with active psychotic symptoms. Physicians judged incapacity in 21.9% of inpatients referred for ECT in Bean et al. (1994/6). This suggests a measurement problem.

Deficits in appreciation ability are reported in both empirical and clinical ethical literature. Some empirical studies additionally report deficits in understanding and reasoning ability. Appelbaum & Grisso (1995 & 1999), Cohen et al. (2004), and Vollman et al. (2003) , all identify understanding and reasoning deficits, with the latter two studies indicating reasoning as the most impaired ability amongst their depressed cohort. Despite these findings, consideration of reasoning ability in relation to DMC is absent from clinical ethical analyses. This may reflect ethical concern that the four abilities model remains too cognitive [4], and that appreciation is the only ability seemingly broad enough to accommodate affective status when judging DMC. Whilst the clinical ethical analyses are well positioned to interpret complex interplay between affect and decision-making abilities it may be that in emphasizing “non-cognitive” abilities in depression, e.g. appreciation, they neglect the impact affect can have on abilities to recall accurately and manipulate information logically. However, the empirical studies that report reasoning impairments more than appreciation impairments are limited by difficulties in the operationalizing of MacCAT-T appreciation (see below). Together these factors could explain why the clinical ethical data and the empirical data show some divergence.

MacCAT appreciation derived from US court rulings during a time when the right to refuse anti-psychotic medication was an important legal issue. Many of these rulings are fairly silent on the detail of appreciation but there is some detail in cases involving schizophrenia where delusions and lack of insight (awareness of illness) were features [27]. Appreciation and insight are often mentioned together. Owen et al. (2009) and Owen et al. (2011) provide evidence that insight is a good indicator of DMC in schizophrenia but a poor one in depression. Grisso and Appelbaum, reflecting on their design of the MacCAT, acknowledge the difficulties they had operationalising appreciation in depression [28]. How depression may impact on the acknowledgement of treatment options, though recognised, is fairly unspecified in the MacCAT-T scoring rules.b .MacCAT appreciation is thus probably better at measuring what is important in schizophrenia than in depression. This may fit with a societal concern not to make the capacity test too sensitive in order to protect liberty interests of patients. Liberty interests, however, need to be balanced against health interests.

Sullivan & Youngner (1994) highlight the demands in assessing appreciative ability; when asking a patient to describe the clinical facts presented, grappling with the pro’s and cons to his or her own life may pose no problem, but when evaluating the patient’s answers to these questions, an assessor may need considerable contextual information and interpretative ability. This might give rise to mis-scoring of the appreciation component of the MacCAT when the contextual and interpretative demands are great – demands which may be high in depressive illness because of the often understandable quality of patients’ decision-making.

Some papers offer potential strategies for dealing with depressed individuals that circumvent assessment of DMC. Rudnick (2002) suggests that consistent treatment preferences should be respected, but, when preferences change, the depressive illness must be alleviated first. Attention has also been drawn to the importance of supported decision-making in which the doctor seeks to enable rather than formally substitute for a depressed patients’ decision–making [22, 29, 30]. Strategies that attempt to minimize the assessment of DMC offer important, but ultimately unsatisfactory solutions to the ethics of treatment in depressed patients. When depressed individuals change their minds about serious treatments, doctors have to consider how they are going to respect their choices; when patients select harmful choices (e.g. self harm, self neglect) physicians may be unable to support their decisions. At such times the assessment of DMC seems impossible to avoid. An ethically grounded, clinically applicable and reliable framework for the assessment of DMC in depression is thus required.

We found legal judgments on DMC involving cases of depression hard to find – especially those involving treatment or research decisions. In England and Wales where courts have judged DMC in persons with depression findings of lack of DMC for treatment exist [31]. In a case occurring after the introduction of the Mental Capacity Act (2005) [32], a depressed woman’s abilities to decide whether to litigate were explicitly judged. Here, the “use or weigh” ability – an ability that overlaps with “appreciation” – was considered relevant in the final judgment of capacity [33]. A systematic legal search and review of DMC cases involving depression may help clarify the legal perspective.

A limitation of the review is its exclusion of ethical analysis in books and book chapters. Our informal review of leading books in contemporary bioethics revealed little additional attention to the relation between depression and DMC. Elliot [34] devotes a book chapter to it but this draws mainly on his paper in this review. Buchanan and Brock [35] in an endnote refer to how a depressed patient may evidence “indifference” to the harmful consequences of his choice (p392). They take this as evidence for the inadequacy of DMC tests that restrict to an understanding ability. We think it unlikely there is a large literature in book form on depression and DMC we are missing.

Conclusion

This review highlights a surprisingly small literature on topics of considerable ethical, clinical and policy importance. However, it shows that a start has been made at researching how DMC in depression can be understood, measured and supported. More rigorous clinical ethical studies aiming to interpret and model appreciation, or similar abilities, in depression are needed because most have been based on clinical experience (risking recycling of clinical opinion instead of generation of new knowledge) or case vignettes (risking inadequate data). The law has not articulated its perspective on appreciation, or similar abilities, owing to a lack of depression cases. There is room to improve understanding and measurement of appreciation and progress should be possible as law, clinical ethics and empirical research gains experience of depression.

Endnotes

aLoss of appreciation and reasoning ability are not acknowledged as relevant abilities in making capacity judgements in some states’ law [1] {26}.

bWhen assessing appreciation, the patient is asked whether they think the treatment may benefit them. The patient’s “yes” or “no” response is not important at this point. Instead, the assessor is seeking to establish whether the patients’ explanation regarding their beliefs about treatment/(research) is based on a delusional premise or a serious distortion of reality. However, in recognition of the difficulty faced in the operationalization of appreciation for affective disorder, the MacCAT-T, the scoring rules for appreciation have an additional note: “failures to acknowledge the potential benefit of treatment may obtain a 0 rating not only if they are based on delusional belief systems, but also if they are strongly influenced by extremes in affective symptoms: e.g. mania, severe depression.” (bold added). ([1] p106 and p184-7).

References

  1. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS: Assessing Competence to Consent to Treatment: A guide for Physicians and Other Health Professionals. 1998, New York: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  2. Owen GS, Richardson G, David AS, Szmukler G, Hayward P, Hotopf M: Mental capacity to make decisions on treatment in people admitted to psychiatric hospitals: cross sectional study. Brit Med J. 2008, 337 (7660): 40-42.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Breden TM, Vollmann J: The cognitive based approach of capacity assessment in psychiatry: a philosophical critique of the MacCAT-T. Health Care Anal. 2004, 12 (4): 273-283. 10.1007/s10728-004-6635-x. discussion 265–272

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Tan JOA, Stewart A, Hope T: Decision-making as a broader concept. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 2009, 16 (4): 345-349. 10.1353/ppp.0.0263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS: Appreciating anorexia: Decisional capacity and the role of values. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology. 2006, 13 (4): 293-301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Owen GS, Freyenhagen F, Richardson G, Hotopf M: Mental Capacity and Decisional Autonomy: An Interdisciplinary Challenge. Inquiry. 2009, 52 (1): 79-107. 10.1080/00201740802661502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Kim SY, Appelbaum PS, Swan J, Stroup TS, McEvoy JP, Goff DC, Jeste DV, Lamberti JS, Leibovici A, Caine ED: Determining when impairment constitutes incapacity for informed consent in schizophrenia research. Br J Psychiatry. 2007, 191: 38-43. 10.1192/bjp.bp.106.033324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Cairns R, Maddock C, Buchanan A, David AS, Hayward P, Richardson G, Szmukler G, Hotopf M: Reliability of mental capacity assessments in psychiatric in-patients. Br J Psychiatry. 2005, 187: 372-378. 10.1192/bjp.187.4.372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Appelbaum PS, Roth LH: Competency to consent to research: a psychiatric overview. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 1982, 39 (8): 951-958. 10.1001/archpsyc.1982.04290080061009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Leeman CP: Depression and the right to die. Gen Hosp Psychiatry. 1999, 21 (2): 112-115. 10.1016/S0163-8343(98)00069-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Elliott C: Caring about risks. Are severely depressed patients competent to consent to research?. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 1997, 54 (2): 113-116. 10.1001/archpsyc.1997.01830140021003.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Halpern J: When concretized emotion-belief complexes derail decision-making capacity. Bioethics. 2012, 26 (2): 108-116. 10.1111/j.1467-8519.2010.01817.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Meynen G: Depression, possibilities, and competence: a phenomenological perspective. Theor Med Bioeth. 2011, 32 (3): 181-193. 10.1007/s11017-010-9171-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Rudnick A: Depression and competence to refuse psychiatric treatment. J Med Ethics. 2002, 28 (3): 151-155. 10.1136/jme.28.3.151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Sullivan MD, Youngner SJ: Depression, Competence, and the Right to Refuse Lifesaving Medical-Treatment. Am J Psychiat. 1994, 151 (7): 971-978.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Young EW, Corby JC, Johnson R: Does depression invalidate competence? Consultants’ ethical, psychiatric, and legal considerations. Camb Q Healthc Ethics. 1993, 2 (4): 505-515. 10.1017/S0963180100004540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Appelbaum PS, Grisso T, Frank E, O’Donnell S, Kupfer DJ: Competence of depressed patients for consent to research. Am J Psychiatry. 1999, 156 (9): 1380-1384.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cohen BJ, McGarvey EL, Pinkerton RC, Kryzhanivska L: Willingness and competence of depressed and schizophrenic inpatients to consent to research. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law. 2004, 32 (2): 134-143.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Bean G, Nishisato S, Rector NA, Glancy G: The psychometric properties of the Competency Interview Schedule. Can J Psychiatry. 1994, 39 (8): 368-376.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Bean G, Nishisato S, Rector NA, Glancy G: The assessment of competence to make a treatment decision: an empirical approach. Can J Psychiatry. 1996, 41 (2): 85-92.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS: Comparison of standards for assessing patients’ capacities to make treatment decisions. Am J Psychiatry. 1995, 152 (7): 1033-1037.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Lapid MI, Rummans TA, Poole KL, Pankratz VS, Maurer MS, Rasmussen KG, Philbrick KL, Appelbaum PS: Decisional capacity of severely depressed patients requiring electroconvulsive therapy. J ECT. 2003, 19 (2): 67-72. 10.1097/00124509-200306000-00002.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Owen GS, David AS, Richardson G, Szmukler G, Hayward P, Hotopf M: Mental capacity, diagnosis and insight in psychiatric in-patients: a cross-sectional study. Psychol Med. 2009, 39 (8): 1389-1398. 10.1017/S0033291708004637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Owen GS, Ster IC, David AS, Szmukler G, Hayward P, Richardson G, Hotopf M: Regaining mental capacity for treatment decisions following psychiatric admission: a clinico-ethical study. Psychol Med. 2011, 41 (1): 119-128. 10.1017/S0033291710000383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Vollmann J, Bauer A, Danker-Hopfe H, Helmchen H: Competence of mentally ill patients: a comparative empirical study. Psychol Med. 2003, 33 (8): 1463-1471. 10.1017/S0033291703008389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Silverstone PH, Salsali M: Low self-esteem and psychiatric patients: Part I–The relationship between low self-esteem and psychiatric diagnosis. Ann Gen Psychiatry. 2003, 2: 2-10.1186/1475-2832-2-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Berg JW, Appelbaum PS, Grisso T: Constructing competence: formulating standards of legal competence to make medical decisions. Rutgers Law Rev. 1996, 48 (2): 345-371.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS: Values and limits of the MacArthur treatment competence study. Psychol Public Pol L. 1996, 2 (1): 167-181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Simon D, Loh A, Wills CE, Harter M: Depressed patients’ perceptions of depression treatment decision-making. Health Expect. 2007, 10 (1): 62-74. 10.1111/j.1369-7625.2006.00424.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Stacey D, Menard P, Gabor I, Jacobsen M, Sharif F, Ritchie L, Bunn H: Decision-making needs of patients with depression: a descriptive study. Journal of Psychiatric & Mental Health Nursing. 2008, 15 (4): 287-295. 10.1111/j.1365-2850.2007.01224.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Rabone and another (Appellants) v Pennine Care NHS Foundation Trust. UKSC 2. 2012

  32. Mental Capacity Act Chapter 9. 2005, London: The Stationary Office

  33. Ganley v Jones. 2011, EWCA Civ, 754-Para (9–22)

  34. Elliot C: A Philosophical Disease: Bioethics. 1999, Culture and Identity: Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  35. Buchanan AE, Brock DW: Deciding for Others. 1990, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

Pre-publication history

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Piers Gooding and Felicity Jones for comments on an earlier draft and Wayne Martin and Fabian Freyenhagen for discussions on the topic of this paper. The Wellcome Trust supported this research.

The Wellcome Trust supported this research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gareth S Owen.

Additional information

Competing interests

The authors declare no conflict of interests.

Authors’ contributions

TH helped design the study, conducted the literature search analysed the results and drafted the manuscript. MH drafted the manuscript. GO designed the study, supervised the literature search, analysed and checked results and drafted the manuscript. All authors read and approved the final manuscript.

Authors’ original submitted files for images

Below are the links to the authors’ original submitted files for images.

Authors’ original file for figure 1

Authors’ original file for figure 2

Rights and permissions

Open Access This article is published under license to BioMed Central Ltd. This is an Open Access article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License ( https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0 ), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hindmarch, T., Hotopf, M. & Owen, G.S. Depression and decision-making capacity for treatment or research: a systematic review. BMC Med Ethics 14, 54 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1186/1472-6939-14-54

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1186/1472-6939-14-54

Keywords